Saturday, July 14, 2018

An Evaluation of Aeschylus’ Agamemnon in the Light Of Aristotle’s Definition of a Perfect Tragedy.




    Aristotle, one of the most versatile thinkers of the ancient world, presented the first technical study of ‘poetry’ in his work Poetics (335 B.C.). Though he has allocated some space for other genres, the core of Poetics is undoubtedly the discussion on tragedy.  Before going further into the discussion, three salient issues on the Aristotelian theory on the perfect tragedy should be set down:
a.       Aristotle’s view on the perfect tragedy is based on Oedipus Tyrannus by Sophocles.
b.      Aristotle shows a tendency of using ‘binary opposites’ in his definition of the perfect tragedy – qualities are mutually exclusive.
c.       Aristotle is not interested in the impact of the tragedy on stage or the aspects related to the performance of a tragedy.
     Continuing the topic under discussion, Aristotle in Poetics proposed the following definition that had been the yardstick in measuring tragedy till the 18th century and continues to exert a considerable influence even today:
“Well then, a tragedy is a mimesis of high, complete action (of proper magnitude), in speech pleasurably enhanced, the different kinds [of enchantment] occurring in separate sections in dramatic, not narrative form, effecting through pity and fear the catharsis of such emotions” (qtd. in Russell 97).
     According to the definition, Aristotle’s view on tragedy is built around the concepts, mimesis and catharsis; all literature is mimesis (imitation)- poets imitates life and produces textual mimesis and the reader is inspired to imitate what s/he reads in the text (audience’s mimesis) which creates pity and fear in her/his mind. Catharsis is the purgation of pity and fear which leads to a pleasurable after effect. Tragic poetry allows the reader to experience alternative and probable lives with aesthetic detachment which enhance her/him emotionally and intellectually. Unlike Plato, Aristotle believes that the ‘artistic taming of the horrible’ is good for the human psyche.
     Analyzing Aeschylus’s Agamemnon, one finds that the play fulfils all the requirements Aristotle demands in a tragedy. The drama contains “a high complete action (of proper magnitude)” which is neither trivial nor vast- the fall of Agamemnon, and “rhythm and harmony of song”; “some parts (dialogues) are in verse alone and others (choral odds) in song” (qtd. in Russell 97). Agamemnon’s tragic flaw (hamartia) is his overriding pride in his accomplishments. His fall, nevertheless, creates pity for him and fear for the reader’s own vulnerability and mortality. These feelings, intensified by the fates of Cassandra and Clytaemnestra, bring about an emotional purging. In the end, the experience of reading/viewing Agamemnon, undoubtedly leads to an emotional and an intellectual edification in the reader/viewer. This, in turn, creates a healthy variety of pleasure in her/his mind.   
     As we have already established the fact that Agamemnon possesses the basic requirements of a tragic play, let us examine if it also has the qualities that constitute a perfect tragedy. According to Aristotle, “A tragedy as a whole will necessarily have six elements, the possession of which makes the tragedy qualitatively distinct [from the other literary kinds]: they are plot, the mimesis of character, verbal expression, mimesis of intellect, spectacle and song writing” (qut. in Russell 97). Let us analyze these elements in relation to Agamemnon to determine if it is, in deed, a perfect tragedy.  


01. Plot/ the first principle (mythos)
     Aristotle says, “A tragedy is [by definition] a mimesis not of people but of their action and life” (qtd. in Russell 98). The mimesis of action – the plot – is the ordering of the particular actions. Therefore, in a perfect tragedy, the plot should be paramount.
     A good plot contains a single line of development that goes from good fortune to bad; the reversal of fortune should arise from the arrangement of actions as is in Agamemnon - the king commits hybris and this allows Clytaemnestra as the instrument of Fate to bring about the reversal of his fortune.
     The action should also be a complete action. The concept of completeness should be analyzed under four subheadings: completeness in order, amplitude, unity, and in probability and necessary connection.
I.      Completeness in order:
     A perfect plot should have “a beginning, middle, and an end” (qut. in Russell 100). Agamemnon begins with Clytaemnestra waiting for the arrival of her husband; in the middle the king arrives, commits hybris and is murdered; the play ends with triumphant Clytaemnestra proposing to Aegisthus that they should rule Argos as co-regents.
     It must be noted that Agamemnon is the first play of a trilogy. Consequently, within the play there are many links to the subsequent plays, The Choephori and The Eumenides. Yet, in itself, Agamemnon is a self-contained whole that does not require the other two plays to be meaningful.
     When it comes to the independence of plot, it does not mean that the play exist in a vacuum. The story of Agamemnon is a part of the myth cycle of the returning (nostos) of the heroes of the Trojan War. The poet has taken the material from the substantial fabric of the myth and developed an independent unit out of it. Still, the poet, beyond doubt, depends on the audience’s knowledge of the basic myth to a considerable degree for the success of the play.
II.      Completeness in amplitude:
     Aristotle says that a tragedy must have “sufficient amplitude to allow a probable or necessary succession of particular action to produce a change from bad to good or from good to bad fortune” (qtd. in Russell 101).
     According to this statement, the extent of the play is determined by the scope of the plot; therefore, it is unrealistic to have a time limit for a play. Agamemnon is, in fact, one of the longest plays among the surviving tragedies, but it contains no more than that can be easily embraced at one sitting. In order to achieve this objective, Aeschylus has selected only what is absolutely necessary of the entire myth of the return of Agamemnon. Events and people (i.e. whereabouts of Electra who plays a key role in The Choephori) that are not strictly necessary to convey the plot are deliberately excluded. Thereby, the focus is unwaveringly fixed on the vital events and the characters, creating an unadulterated impact on the reader/viewer.
III.      Completeness in unity:
     According to Aristotle a “ plot, being a mimesis of action, should be a mimesis of one action that a whole one, with different sections so arranged that the wholeness is disturbed by the transposition and destroyed by the removal of one of them” (qtd. in Russell 101). Therefore, each event in a perfect tragedy is located precisely within its framework in such way that it cannot be shuffled or omitted without causing a significant damage to the entire plot.
     This criterion is very much applicable to the plot of Agamemnon. The watchman appears only once at the very beginning of the play, but there is no question of the relevance of his soliloquy to the success of the play. It is the watchman who sets the mood for the entire play and provides a powerful picture of the formidable Queen Clytaemnestra in “whose woman’s heart/ A man’s will nurses hope” (Vellacott 41). He reveals the ingenious method through which Clytaemnestra learns about the fall of Troy so that she would not be taken unawares by the return of her husband. The watchman also broadly hints at the less-than-warm welcome in store for the returning king. Therefore, it is essential that the watchman should deliver the prologue.
     Cassandra, sitting silently on the carriage upon arrival, seems quite superfluous - at least in the text. Her tragically majestic presence would undoubtedly present a greater impact on stage. But the very next instance, Aeschylus needs her prophetic prowess to reveal what is going on behind the closed doors of the palace and to keep the events rolling. In effect, Cassandra links the past, the present and the future. The poet also makes use of her dialogue with the Chorus of Elders to air the contemporary views on sin/retribution and revenge/justice as groundwork for the subsequent events.
     Cassandra also presents a foil to Clytaemnestra. While the Argive Queen rages against her fate and fights it, the Trojan Princess calmly accepts a greater tragedy; she has lost her family, home as well as her freedom, and she is about to be murdered in cold blood.
     The same concept of relevance applies to Aegisthus as well. Though he appears at the very end of the drama his presence is felt throughout. It is fit that he should play his role behind the scene and appear on stage only after the deed is done.
     Considering the above evidence, it is clear that all events in Agamemnon are absolutely necessary and they appear in the right order.
IV.      Completeness in probability and necessary connection:
     M. E. Hubbard commenting on the Aristotelian definition in Ancient Literary Criticism says that the poet “cannot say anything that his audience will not take to be relevant to the picture they assume he is presenting” (qtd. in Russell102). 
    According to Aristotle, the tragedian faced a unique situation in choosing material. The story and the characters in his play, the heroes and the gods of the Greek mythology, were a part of the state religion that was still in practice in his society. Therefore, a tragedy could not destroy the basic framework of the received myth while it may change the non-essential elements. 
     In Agamemnon, Aeschylus, maintains the basic myth. But unlike the historian, who is duty-bound to include incidents that fit as well as those that do not, the poet picks only those events that are conducive to his purpose. Other than a passing reference to Theystes as the “the defiler of his brother’s bed” by Cassandra, why Atreus chose to serve the abominable meal to his brother is left unexplained without causing any damage to the plot (84). It is taken for granted that the audience already knows the reason. Also, contrary to the accepted myth, in Agamemnon, Aegisthus is the full brother to the dead children. The reason for this is, while Aegisthus’ parentage may be a critical issue in Theystes, it does not have the same implication to Agamemnon. So Aeschylus, by modifying this minor fact, makes Aegisthus the rightful avenger of his brothers, unburdened by an incestuous birth.
     The element of probability and necessity is strongest when the Chorus of Elders refuses to understand the clues given by Clytaemnestra as to her intention to kill Agamemnon. She is quite plain when she says:
“If the fleet sails free from the taint of sin, the gods
May grant them safely to retrace their outward course
Those whom no watchful anger of forgotten deed
Waits to surprise with vengeance…” (54)    
To this the chorus replies, “Madam, your words are like a man’s, both wise and kind” (55). Taken independently, the response of the Chorus seems quite ridiculous. But taken within the context of the play, the Chorus seems to believe that upon his arrival, Agamemnon would take matters into his hand and put Clytaemnestra back in her proper place. This understanding seems to prevent the Elders from taking the Queen seriously, thus the patronizing reply quoted above.
     With regard to Cassandra’s prophecies, it is almost absurd the way the Chorus fails to understand her. The Trojan Prophetess, when driven to it, most emphatically says, “I say Agamemnon shall lie dead before your eyes” (85). Still the Chorus would not believe her. Here, if the Chorus understood her and took action, then the murder of Agamemnon would not have taken place – the result would be a tragedy with a different ending. Therefore, Aeschylus makes use of Apollo’s curse which not only explains why the Chorus would not believe her but also creates a great deal of pathos for the plight of the captive princess.
     In conclusion of this section of the analysis, it is clear that Agamemnon addresses all the requirements of completeness in the plot in order, amplitude, unity and probable and necessary connection of events.
     The best kind of plot according to Aristotle is the complex type “in which change of fortune is accompanied by peripeteia (reversal) or recognition (anagnorisis) or both… The peripeteia and recognition should arise just from the arrangement of the plot” (qtd. in Russell 104).
     Despite its seemingly simple linear plot, Agamemnon is a highly complex play. It is true that the tragic hero himself experiences only an almost imperceptible moment of peripeteia, but it is this sheer brevity that makes the moment hauntingly piercing. Agamemnon, who returns home unhurt from a ten-year-long war, seems have assumed that the gods have forgiven him for the sin of shedding kindred blood in the sacrifice of his daughter Iphigenia. He also seems to have disassociated himself from the inherited family curse. In reality, this is natural for a man at the height of glory. It is this supremely confident man who awaits the ritual cleansing at the altar in his palace so he could resume the mantle of kingship and live the rest of his life basking in the glory of his victory. And it is also at this giddy pinnacle must Agamemnon have realized that nothing is ever forgiven or forgotten. He must have understood that his hamartia has led him to commit sins of his own free will which are compounded by the murder of Iphigenia, violation of Cassandra, the family curse and destiny. The all too brief space of time allocated to Agamemnon’s peripeteia is different from the full-blown, drawn-out one experienced by Oedipus; nevertheless, it is exactly the type of the peripeteia required by the plot of Agamemnon. It would be quite unrealistic for Aeschylus to allow Agamemnon to explore the turn of his fortune and the reality of his fall in leisure as the plot requires him to die, and die quickly; thus, the absence of an articulated anagnorisis following Agamemnon’s brief peripeteia.
     In the play both Cassandra and Clytaemnestra experience peripeteia and anagnorisis. Cassandra’s experience of the reversal and recognition is quite conspicuous. The Trojan princess must have reached the height of her existence when she became a priestess and a prophetess of Apollo, but has she consciously committed a sin in refusing the Archer God: “I gave my word, and broke it – to the God of Words” (84). She acknowledges her fate – “there is no escape, none – once the hour has come” (87). The heroic manner in which Cassandra accepts her fate elevates her even above Agamemnon, the tragic hero of the play.   
     Clytemnestra’s peripeteia and anagnorisis occur towards the very end of the play. The nervous tension brought on by the single-handed execution of the murder plot, the relentless accusations of the Chorus, the ‘death-song’ of Cassandra, and her own awareness of how justice works have done the damage. The Queen realizes that her comeuppance is not far off. This is why she, in preventing Aegisthus from ordering the soldiers to attack the Elders, says:
“When this first harvest ripens we’ll reap grief enough
Crime and despair are fed to bursting; let s not
Plunge deeper still in blood” (100)
     The result of the three sets of peripeteia and anagnorisis is pity for all three characters. A man as great as Agamemnon is brought low at the height of his might; Cassandra, a princess of mighty Troy, enslaved, dies far away from home un-mourned; regal Clytaemnestra, the wronged mother and scorned wife, according to Cassandra, would be killed by her own son. Destiny spares no one, not even the larger-than-life individuals like Agamemnon, Clytaemnestra, and Cassandra. This truth inevitably creates fear in the mind of the reader leading to the catharsis of the both pity and fear.
    Aristotle commenting on the source of the perfect tragic effect says:
“Pity and fear can be elicited by the spectacle, they can also be elicited by the arrangement of the particular action [that make up the plot], and this is superior consideration and the sign of a better plot…for the plot ought to be so composed that even without seeing the action, a man who just hears what is going on shudders and feels pity because of what happens” (qtd. in Russell 108).
     In Agamemnon, denouement and the resulting pity and fear, as discussed above, are unquestionably elicited by the arrangement of the actions of the plot; characters only serve to deliver the requirements of the plot. It is inevitable that the reader should feel pity for the destinies of all the characters in the play and fear for the mutability of his/her own fortune in comparison despite the passage of many centuries separating her/him from the characters in the play.
     Aristotle also says that a poet must look for cases where “the pathos involves people closely connected” (qtd. in Russell 108). In Agamemnon, a father kills a daughter to be in turn killed by the mother of the dead child. There is also the implication that the mother herself will be murdered in retaliation by her own son.
     Aristotelian analysis divides the plot as ‘complication’ and ‘dénouement’. In a perfect tragedy, the dénouement is resultant of the reversal and/or recognition, and the best type of recognition occurs when the tragic hero “might through ignorance intend to do something irreparable, and then recognize the victim-to-be before doing it” and thereby, “give up the course of action” (qtd. in Russell 109). But M. E. Hubbard in a footnote to the quote points out that this type of situations lead to happy endings as in Iphigenia in Tauris of Euripides which in essence is a tragi-comedy.
He further adds that this alludes to a change in the theatre- tradition from pure tragedy to tragi-comedy.
    In Agamemnon, all actions are conscious decisions; the killer kills a known victim with the full intention of seeing the action through to the bitter end. This ‘discrepancy’ in the play, instead of reducing it, amplifies the effect of the anagnorisis. If those who are nearest and dearest wield a knife against one, then where can one turn for a haven in the troubled waters of life?         
02. Mimesis of Character (ethos)
     To Aristotle, it is “[the mimesis of] the moral character of the personages, namely that [in the play] which makes us say that the agents have certain moral qualities” (qtd. in Russell 97).
     Tragic characters, according to Aristotle, should be judged by two qualities – thought and action. The qualities a person is born with and those s/he develops in the course of a lifetime shape her/his thought while happiness or wretchedness, on the other hand, is determined by her/his actions. As in Agamemnon, a good tragedy is mimesis of those actions at a critical point.
     A perfect tragedy has a ‘double thread’ – two groups of people who meet with opposite ends due to the differences in their nature- thought and action. The play is basically a struggle (agon) between these two character types. In Agamemnon, the central agon is between Agamemnon and Clytaemnestra. In addition, if the chorus is to be considered as an actor as Aristotle posits, then the Chorus of Elders become party to a pair of agons with Clytaemnestra and Cassandra. Though brief, the agon between the Queen and Cassandra is also very important to the plot of the play.    
     Agamemnon is the tragic hero as indicated by the title of the play. Aristotle, in defining the nature of the tragic hero says: “He is one who is not pre-eminent in moral virtue, who passes to bad fortune not through vice or wickedness, but because of some piece of ignorance, and who is of high repute and great good fortune, like Oedipus and Theystes and the splendid men of such families” (qtd. in Russell 106).
     Agamemnon fits the description on all but one count. He is a descendent of an established royal line and had been the commander-in-chief of the army that defeated Troy. He enters the stage at the height of his fortune. When it comes to ‘virtue’, one should be careful not to cloud his/her vision with the current interpretation of the term. To the Greeks of the Heroic Age, virtue equalled stature; therefore, whatever Agamemnon did in his capacity as the king and the commander (as long as it does not violate the divine code of justice) was right and good. At Chalkis, when the fleet was prevented from sailing by the adverse winds sent by Artemis, Agamemnon had to make a choice:
o   Sacrifice Iphigenia and obtain fair winds, or
o   Give up the expedition and disband the army
Agamemnon’s pride, his hamartia, prevented him from making the second choice which was the ethically right one. He was unwilling to disband the army due to the fear of earning a deserter’s badge which would in turn force him to give up the command of the alliance. Therefore, he rationalized sacrificing Iphigenia by saying:
“Their chafing rage demands it – they are right
May good prevail, and justify my dead!” (49)
Agamemnon failed to see that he had actually failed the test and by making the wrong choice committed a sin that would make him ripe for retribution. Vellacott in the introduction to The Oresteian Trilogy says that the Chorus points out that Fate is not concrete; instead, Fate gives man a choice, and invariably he chooses wrongly due to his hamartia and commits a sin. According to M. E. Hubbard, Aristotle points to hamartia as the cause of the misfortune of the tragic hero. In this capacity, the outcome of the hamartia has to fulfil two requirements:
  • In order to avoid Justified Indignation in the audience at the undeserved misfortune of a good person, the hero should in some sense be responsible for his action
  • To avoid Justified Pleasure in the audience at the deserved misfortune of a wicked person, the hero’s fate should be worse than what he deserved
Hamartia, in this respect, is a venal action the hero is unaware of committing, for a sin committed with knowledge is also a crime.
     Yet, Agamemnon cannot plead ignorance in his defence; all four of his sins - sacrifice of Iphigenia, defilement of Cassandra, inviting the gods to share his glory and treading on the crimson silk cloth – are done with full knowledge. At the same time, it is this awareness that makes the plight of the Argive King more poignant. It is clear that Agamemnon is aware of the gravity of at least the last of his sins when he says: “May no watchful envious god/ Glance from afar…” (75). But his destiny and the in-built tragic flaw prevent him from reversing the course of actions that is so obviously leading to his downfall.
     Strangely enough, both the Chorus and Cassandra do not seem to hold Agamemnon’s sins as serious as the single act Clytaemnestra commits out of necessity as much as from the desire to avenge her affronted wifehood and motherhood. The reason for this the concept of royal goodness - as the king, Agamemnon will be excused of many acts that would be frowned upon in others and still be called good. Therefore, it is ironic that Agamemnon fails to draw the same amount of pity Cassandra and Clytaemnestra draw. The reason for this lies in the way the characters are depicted. The male is depicted as vainglorious and abrasive while the females stand tragically noble. And this would be a good opportunity to move the discussion to the four qualities required by Aristotle in the characters of a good tragedy: moral goodness, suitability, life-likeness, and consistency.
I.      The character represented should be morally good:
According to Aristotle, “The character represented will be good if the choice is good” (qtd. in Russell 110). As the ‘goodness’ of Agamemnon is already established, let us look at his queen. Clytaemnestra has been unfaithful to her husband and kills him upon his return. This is hardly the picture of a virtuous Greek woman. But a deeper examination of the portrayal of the character of the Queen in the play shows that Clytaemnestra acts the way she does out of necessity. As the mother of Iphigenia, it is Clytemnestra’s duty to avenge her death. If she did not, the Avenging Furies would victimize her.
     Under these circumstances, it is obvious Aeschylus does not propose to brand Clytaemnestra as a heartless villain. As she aptly points out, “dressed in (her) form, a phantom/ Of vengeance has taken revenge for sins old and new” (94). According to Aeschylus’ portrayal, Clytaemnestra is ultimately an instrument of Justice, Furies, and Destiny; therefore, her action, in itself, is not evil.
II.      The character represented should be suitable:
     “The character represented is brave (and therefore, meets the requirement of being morally good), but it is not suitable for a woman to be brave or clever this way” (qtd. in Russell 110). When examining Agamemnon, the king as the conqueror of Troy is undoubtedly brave, therefore, morally good. The watchman, the chorus and the herald make repeated references to Agamemnon’s goodness. The herald says:
“To you and every Argive citizen, Agamemnon
Brings light in darkness” (61)
According to Aristotle’s definition, his goodness and stature makes Agamemnon ideal hero material.
     Aeschylus’s female characters, on the other hand, do not comply with the Aristotelian definition of moral goodness. Both Clytaemnestra and Cassandra are fully developed tragic characters. The Argive queen is intelligent and assertive. Clytaemnestra by nature is not someone who would accept being wronged or belittled lying down. As depicted by Aeschylus, the heroic spirit of her age is very much alive in the Queen; unfortunately, being a woman, Clytaemnestra does not have the means to explore it.  Aeschylus repeatedly proves Clytemnestra’s superiority over the other characters - with the possible exception of Cassandra - through out the play. The Argive Queen is a brilliant tactician. She knows her weaknesses and strengths. In the male dominated world she is a part of, Clytaemnestra needs the helping hand of a man, and who would be better than Aegisthus, another victim of the House of Atreus? Through her illicit affair with Aegisthus, Clytaemnestra acquires a helpmate in carrying out her revenge plot. Nothing is left to chance; Clytaemnestra devices a method to learn of the fall of Troy in advance and weaves the special robe that would entrap her husband for his execution upon his arrival. It is the Queen that compels Agamemnon to walk on the crimson silk despite his apparent reluctance. Towards the end, she almost compels the Chorus to acknowledge that it is just for a sinner to be killed. The play closes with Clytaemnestra proposing to Aegisthus that they should be co-regents.  P. Vellacott in the introduction to The Oresteian Trilogy says, “The deepest spring of her tragedy is the knowledge that she, who has it in her to be the head of a kingdom, if need be, as well as of a family, can be freely ignored as a wife and outraged as a mother by a man she knows her inferior” (22).
     Cassandra proves her astuteness when she alone realizes the real meaning behind Clytemnestra’s victory cry. She is brave in the way she calmly accepts the inevitable and walks into the palace to meet her death: “I have done with tears, I will endure my death” (87).
     The fact that female characters do not meet the specification given by Aristotle at a much later date does not diminish the stature of Agamemnon as an ideal tragedy. A powerful man like Agamemnon needs an equally or more powerful enemy to bring about his downfall, and Clytaemnestra – said to be a daughter of Zeus in some myths – is just that, a strong enemy who incidentally  is a woman.
III.      The character should be lifelike:
     Here The Poetics does not specify what Aristotle meant by the term ‘life-like’. In his discussion on poetic imagination Aristotle says, “(F)or given natural endowments, people who actually feels passion are the most convincing” (qtd. in Russell 113). All major characters in Agamemnon have the larger-than-life quality inherent in ideal tragic characters. Despite this, Agamemnon, Clytaemnestra, and Cassandra are compellingly lifelike in the way they think, speak, and behave.
     Agamemnon as a returning hero of the Trojan War is full of himself and invites gods to share his glory. The abandoned wife and the wronged mother in Clytaemnestra thirst for revenge. In Cassandra, the final rebellion against Apollo when she tramples on her prophetic insignia is quite natural. After all, what can be more frustrating than to know everything to happen and not being able to prevent even one’s own death?
IV.      The character should be consistent:
     “In the representation of character…one ought to look for the necessary or probable, so that it is necessity or probable that a person like this speaks or acts as he does” (qtd. in Russell 110/11).
     Looking at Agamemnon, all characters match this requirement. Agamemnon’s behaviour as the proud, blustering patriarch of the House of Atreus - as seen in the way he invites the gods to share his glory and the dismissive tone he uses to address his wife - is quite consistent throughout the parts he physically appears. Aeschylus’s characterization of Agamemnon is consistent with that of Homer in The Iliad and The Odyssey, too. Any sense of inconsistency is due to the fact that the reality of Agamemnon does not match the extraordinary hero-king created by the watchman, the chorus, and the herald through the images of hunting lions and soaring eagles. When it comes to their rulers, people often seem to blur the difference between the reality and the ideal.
     The caricatures of Cassandra and Clytaemnestra found in the myths are shaped by Aeschylus into full-bodied, dynamic characters. Yet, they retain the essential qualities that have been allocated to them in the myths. Clytaemnestra is the vengeful, adulterous wife and Cassandra continues to be the unfortunate priestess of Apollo whose prophecies no one believes.
     Aristotelian definition of a perfect tragedy requires the dénouement of the plot to arise from the mimesis of character, not from dues-ex-machina. Dependence on such external features, according to the critic, would ally the plot with the spectacle rather than poetry which is usually a mark of poor craftsmanship. In this respect, in Agamemnon, Cassandra’s prophesies given to her by Apollo can be construed as a type of dues-ex-machina, but a closer examination reveals that the prophecies do not bring about any change in the plot proper. Their only function is to create tension and pathos as events spiral into a culmination behind the scene. Ultimately, the denouement in Agamemnon arises from the actions of the characters whose fates are locked on a collision course and not by the caprice of any god that descends timely from the episkene.    
03. Mimesis of Intellect (dianoia)
     “Mimesis,” according to Aristotle, “is their (characters’) ability to say what the situation requires …those passages in which they prove that something is or is not the case or deliver themselves of some general statement” (qtd. in Russell 99).
     The main instrument used in producing the mimesis of intellect is speech. “Its sections are proof and disproof, rousing emotions (pity, fear, anger, and so on), making a thing look important or unimportant” (qtd. in Russell 116). According to M. E. Hubbard, here, Aristotle is referring to the characters making use of persuasive language in order to elicit a specific reaction from other characters. According to the definition, when speech is used, effects should emerge from the speech itself without the necessity of accompanying actions.
     In Aeschylus’s plays, in general, the mimesis of intellect is the main tool used by characters to elicit reactions from one other. In fact, Aeschylus uses both speech and the absence of speech as tools. Clytaemnestra and Cassandra’s long silence upon entering the stage are ridiculed by Euripides in Aristophanes’ Frogs, but a closer examination of the plot reveals that their silence in fact speaks volumes. Clytaemnestra stands imperially aloof at her prayers and speaks only when she chooses to despite earnest requests to do so by the Chorus of Elders. Thereby, the Queen asserts her superiority over the Elders. The reader/viewer realizes that Clytaemnestra is no weeping Penelope but a strong assertive woman. Cassandra stays tragically silent among the booty on the second chariot that arrives with Agamemnon and refuses to speak even when directly addressed to by Clytaemnestra who by then has outsmarted the hero himself. This is the only incident in the play in which Clytaemnestra is truly bested.
     When they choose to speak, all characters use language in such a way that the desired effect is created by the spoken word alone without the necessity of the support of accompanying actions. The best example in the play for mimesis of intellect is the agon between Agamemnon and Clytaemnestra between lines 857 – 957. Here, Clytaemnestra uses a series of arguments and counter-arguments to convince Agamemnon that he should walk on the crimson silk cloth. Embedded in her lines, are messages that should rouse fear and call for caution in anyone who is a little less sure of himself than Agamemnon. The reader/viewer, on the other hand, is all too aware of the rage of the Queen hidden behind the highly metaphorical utterances. Between lines 856 – 892, Clytaemnestra refers to Agamemnon’s death five times and she ends by saying:
 “……….Justice herself
Shall lead him to a home he never hoped to see
All other matters fore thought, never lulled by sleep,
Shall order justly as the will of Heaven decrees” (73)
     Upon being snubbed by Agamemnon, she resumes the seemingly subservient persuasion and talks of “purple dye” and “stores of crimson” – which according to Vellacott, are references to blood and the family curse. Towards the end, she talks of “unripe grape” being pressed to make wine – a reference to the sacrifice of Iphigenia. The entire sequence of exchanges between the king and the queen is a test of wills, and ultimately, despite his blustering, it is Agamemnon who gives in. according to P. Vellacott, Clytaemnestra achieves three objectives by making Agamemnon walk on the crimson silk:
a.       Establishes her superiority over her husband
b.      Makes Agamemnon feel guilty
c.       Makes the audience aware that the ultimate responsibility of the fate of Agamemnon lies in his own actions
     Clytaemnestra once again uses her intellect to bend the Chorus of Elders to listen to her side of the story in their exchange of words after the murder. In the end the Chorus almost concedes:
“Reproach answer reproach; truth darkens still
She strikes the striker; he who dares to kill
Pays the full forfeit. While Zeus holds his throne,
This maxim holds on earth: the sinner dies” (96) 
     Cassandra’s futile efforts to make the Chorus see the impending disaster and their subsequent bewilderment are also examples of mimesis of intellect.
     The chorus through their long choral odds and incessant questioning irritate both Clytaemnestra and Cassandra and make them speak; their conversations are means through which a lot of information on their state of mind and intentions come into light.  
04. Verbal Expression (lexis)
     Composition of the verse part of the dialogue is called the verbal expression. According to Aristotle, elements, syllables, linking words, articulatory words, nouns, terminations and statements are the parts constituent of verbal expression. Verbal expression is good, according to Poetics, if the poetry involved is “clear without being mean” (qtd. in Russell 121). In order to achieve clarity devoid of meanness, the poet should strive for a proper mixture of strange expressions (dialect terms, metaphors, etc.) and the standard words. This way, strange expressions will keep the style from being commonplace and the standard words would help to maintain the clarity.
     As we are dealing with a translation of the Agamemnon, it is unproductive to analyze the elements, syllables, linking words, etc. of the English text in this regard. Yet, it is a credit to the skills of the translators that some of the often talked about Aeschylian grandeur in verbal expression has survived the translation for the gratification of the readers who are not conversant in the language of the original text. As a reference to what the other poets thought of the verbal expression of Aeschylus’ dramas, it is worth looking at Euripides’ criticism of Aeschylus in the Frogs for redundancy and bombast. 
     Nevertheless, there is one aspect which falls under strange expressions, that can be examined for its effectiveness even in the translated form, and that is the use of imagery, especially metaphors and similes. According to Aristotle, the use of metaphor is the only aspect of verbal expression that cannot be learnt; it is something inherent in a poet. Aeschylus is clearly a poet that does not suffer from a dearth in this respect, for he uses a large number of metaphors and similes that quite majestically and clearly drives home the desired effect. One of the most chilling metaphors used by Clytaemnestra refers to the impending doom of her husband:
            “…but when Zeus
From the unripe grape presses his wine, then through the house
Heat dies, and coolness comes, as through this royal door
Enters its lord, perfected, to receive his own” (74)
Later on Clytaemnestra compares Cassandra to a newly captured wild mare when she refuses to answer her or get off the carriage:
“Yet has not sense enough to accept her owner’s bit
Till she has frothed her rage out from a bloody mouth” (79)
Cassandra’s analysis of happiness also falls under the use of metaphor:
“…..man’s happiest hours
Are pictures drawn in shadow. Then ill fortune comes,
And with two strokes the wet sponge wipes the drawing out
And grief itself’s hardly more pitiable than joy” (88)
     As it is beyond my capacity to do justice to this section of the argument at present due to lack knowledge in the original Greek text, let us turn towards the remaining sections.
     To Aristotle the art of tragedy is inherent in the structure of the written text; therefore, he does not consider the performative context of a tragedy as important.  According to this concept, both song writing (melos) and spectacle (opsis) are devices that cater to pleasure alone, therefore, they do not have much in common with the art of poetry. As a result, Aristotle does not say much about song writing and spectacle in his analysis of the elements that constitute a perfect tragedy.
     Coral odds make up the entirety of song writing (melos) in tragedy. Aristotle considers the treatment of the chorus as a necessary element of a perfect tragedy. According to his definition, “one should regard the chorus too as one of the actors, and as a part of the whole and taking part in the action” (qtd. in Russell 116). This is true of the chorus of Agamemnon. Typical of Aeschylus’ plays, the Chorus of Elders enjoy the loin’s share of the 1673–line drama. They enter just after the entrance of Clytaemnestra; briefly leave to mark the passage of time between the sighting of the beacons and the arrival of the king, and immediately return just before the arrival of the herald. Thereafter, the chorus stays till the end of the play. Agamemnon’s chorus mostly speak as a unit in long beautifully crafted choral odds. They use these odds to convey the poet’s philosophy/world view, give background information, warn/ encourage characters, etc. Through their interactions with the characters, the chorus assists the progress of the play from one stage to another. Consequently, the role of the chorus, as Aristotle defines, is as essential to the play as any of the other characters.
     According to Poetics, the spectacle is the least to do with the art of poetry. The reason for this is that the art of the stage designer adds more to the excellence of the spectacle than the poet does. For Aristotle special effects such as costumes, sounds, etc. cannot make up for a bad plot.
      Agamemnon, beyond doubt, fits the Aristotelian requirement of non reliance on song writing and spectacle. The text, as amply proven by the heated discussions it initiated in WCC 201 lectures on the drama, does not require a public performance, players or the art of the stage designers; the written word itself, through the sheer power of the plot and characterization, carries the reader along and creates a stage in his/her mind’s eye where the play comes to vibrant life.  This is clearly pointed out by the relative scarcity of the stage instructions included in the text itself. Aeschylus obviously relies very little on the stage craft to convey his fare. Props such as the small mattress, lights, sacrifice things, two chariots and spoils of war, crimson silk cloth, emblem of Cassandra, the bloody weapon and bodies wheeled out on the ekkyklema undoubtedly would be impressive on stage, but their absence does not reduce the strength of the poet’s delivery whatsoever in Agamemnon. Moreover, Agamemnon does not make use of the spectacle to bring about the resolution; the plot inexorably moves towards the denouement on its own strength.
     Lastly, Aristotle says that a perfect tragedy should be a combination of the four subspecies of tragedy:
a.       complex tragedy
b.      tragedy of pathos
c.       tragedy of character
d.      tragedy of spectacle
     Agamemnon does combine a fair dose of all four of the types of tragedies listed above. It has, as discussed above, a complex plot that contains not one but three peripeteia; like Ajax of Sophocles, the play contains ample quantities of tragedy of pathos and character. The sight of triumphant Clytaemnestra wielding a bloody knife standing over the pitiful remains of her victims should add a healthy dose of spectacle to the play despite the lack of gods descending from above and ghosts appearing from below.
          Taking all the above discussed features such as the excellence in plot, the mimesis of character, the verbal expression, and the mimesis of intellect and the relative unimportance placed on the spectacle and song writing, it is patent that Agamemnon is a perfect tragedy. Any ‘discrepancies’ one may note in Aeschylus’ play arise from the three points stated at the very beginning of the discussion which are actually weaknesses of the Aristotelian model of a perfect tragedy according to many critics such as M. E. Hubbard.
a.       By presenting Oedipus, the King as his ideal, Aristotle enters the discussion with a prejudice which is quite crippling in a highly individualistic field such as drama.
b.      Secondly, discrepancies also arise from the mutually exclusive nature of Aristotelian criteria - Clytaemnestra cannot be a woman and be heroic at the same time.
c.       Thirdly, Aeschylus has included features such as the majestic silent figures of Clytaemnestra and Cassandra, the sight of the booty piled up on the chariot, and Agamemnon walking towards his doom on the crimson carpet that are under Aristotelian model would be listed as irrelevant performative aspects. A closer examination would reveal that these features, in truth, enrich the drama instead of reducing its quality.
Therefore, dissimilarities the play display with regard mimesis of character, placement of multiple peripeteia ands anagnorisis, etc to the Aristotelian model, in reality, adds to the success of the play rather than reducing its quality as a perfect tragedy.
Works Cited
Aeschylus. The Oresteian Trilogy. Trans. Philip Vellacott. Middlesex: Penguin, 1968.
Mathews, Roy T., and F. Dewitt Platt, Readings in the Western Humanities. New York: McGraw-Hill, 2004.   
Russell, D. A., and M. Winterbottom. ed. Ancient Literary Criticism. Oxford: Clarendon, 1978.
Other Reference Material
“Aristotle. Poetics. Trans. S. H. Butcher. London: Macmillan, 1932.
“The Plot Of Aeschylus's Agamemnon Based On Aristotle's Poetics” <http://www.oppapers.com/essays/Plot-Aeschyluss-Agamemnon-Based-Aristotles-Poetics/173290>

2 comments:

  1. This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.

    ReplyDelete

The “humour” poems in our syllabus while providing humour, attempt to convey some greater truths. Discuss this statement with relevance to three poems in your syllabus:

  The term “humour” is often associated with silliness, meaninglessness, lack of depth, etc. Therefore, when a poem receives the “appellatio...